Gary R,
Yes, that quote at the end of your post (CP2.231, also EP2:282-3) is worth
reflecting on in this context; but then that's true of the whole Speculative
Grammar section of the Syllabus. Every time I read part of it, it seems that
another word in the crossword puzzle gets filled in, because of clues I've
picked up since the previous reading. This time around, what comes to the
fore is that the interpretant of a dicisign or proposition represents the
sign itself as well as its object, and represents it as an index - which,
strictly speaking, lacks the generality which makes the argument a symbol
and thus more genuine. I'm not making it any more clear than Peirce did,
just rewording it, but that seems to help make the words more transparent,
so that we can see through them to what we're talking about. Maybe that's
why Peirce did so much rewording of his own thought - to get through to the
real, general, genuine Thought that was not merely his, and not merely his
momentary brain activity, but a piece of the Truth .
But then I must be missing something too, because I don't see why Peirce's
remark that "A proof or genuine argument is a mental process which is open
to logical criticism" is in any way incompatible with the notion that the
dicisign might be described as 'degenerate' relative to the argument. Can
you maybe reword that part of your message?
gary f.
From: Gary Richmond [mailto:***@gmail.com]
Sent: 30-Sep-14 7:11 PM
To: ***@lists.ut.ee
Cc: Peirce List
Subject: [biosemiotics:7038] Re: Natural Propositions, Chapter 3.3
Gary, lists,
GF: By shifting the emphasis (in his definition of "fact") from that
Secondness to its structure - which is that of a proposition or dicisign,
and therefore partakes of Thirdness - I think Peirce was adding another
dimension to the mode of being of "fact".
I would tend to agree that Peirce did indeed add exactly this new dimension
to the mode of being a fact in his reflections ca. 1904, moving from his
late 19th century emphasis on its existential 2ns to examining its structure
as a dicisign at the beginning of the 20th.
Continuing with our ongoing analysis of genuineness and degeneracy in this
regard, you wrote regarding a passage you quoted (EP2:274):
GF: [That t]his shows at least that genuineness and degeneracy are not
absolute qualities but always relative to a function. So even though Peirce
gave the icon and index the "disparaging name" of "degenerate" in KS, he
also pointed out that they (especially when combined!) can carry out
semiotic functions that the symbol is incapable of except by involving them.
Yes, no doubt mathematical ideas related to degeneracy can help us overcome
a linguistic tendency to think perhaps a bit disparagingly of degeneracy in
semiotic relations when such is not at all Peirce's intent. But this is
still a vexing issue for me. For example, you wrote:
GF: I wonder, too, if the dicisign and the proposition itself can be
described as "degenerate" relative to the argument, which is the most
complete and complex of all sign-types because it separately indicates its
interpretant - and which, for that very reason, can only be a symbol. Is
that the main reason why the symbol is the most genuine member of the first
(icon/index/symbol) trichotomy of signs?
But in looking for telling passages related to "genuine" relations, I came
across this.
A proof or genuine argument is a mental process which is open to logical
criticism. CP 2.26
Perhaps one needn't make too much of this apparent equivalence of 'proof'
and 'genuine argument', but it does make me abit unsure about your thought
that the dicisign might be "described as 'degenerate' relative to the
argument." I think there may be good reasons to think that that's a pretty
good abduction, but I'm not yet entirely convinced.
At CP 5.76 Peirce refers to the symbol as the "relatively genuine form of
Representamen" in relation to the index and the icon. Again one needn't make
too much of the phrase 'relatively genuine', but I'm not exactly certain now
how much to make of it. Maybe it simply means what we've always taken it to
mean in this context, but why then "relatively"?
As for the 'genuine index' in consideration of the dicisign, although you
(or Frederik?) may have already quoted some of this passage, I found it of
the greatest interest, although I not quite yet sure exactly what to make of
it.
. . . Now in analyses hitherto proposed, it seems to have been thought that
if assertion [. . .] were omitted, the proposition would be
indistinguishable from a compound general term--that "A man is tall" would
then reduce to "A tall man." It therefore becomes important to inquire
whether the definition of a Dicisign here found to be applicable to the
former [. . .] may not be equally applicable to the latter. The answer,
however, comes forthwith. Fully to understand and assimilate the symbol "a
tall man," it is by no means requisite to understand it to relate [. . .] to
a real Object. Its Interpretant, therefore, does not represent it as a
genuine Index; so that the definition of the Dicisign does not apply to it.
It is impossible here fully to go into the examination of whether the
analysis given does justice to the distinction between propositions and
arguments. But it is easy to see that the proposition purports to intend to
compel its Interpretant to refer to its real Object, that is represents
itself as an Index, while the argument purports to intend not compulsion but
action by means of comprehensible generals, that is, represents its
character to be specially symbolic (CP 2.321, emphasis added).
I want to spend more time reflecting on this passage in consideration of
"the distinction between propositions and arguments" as it seems to me to be
of potential considerable importance in our reflections on the dicisign.
I'll be interested to hear what you or other members of the lists make of
this quotation.
Best,
Gary
Gary Richmond
Philosophy and Critical Thinking
Communication Studies
LaGuardia College of the City University of New York
C 745
718 482-5690
On Mon, Sep 29, 2014 at 2:53 PM, Gary Fuhrman <***@gnusystems.ca> wrote:
Gary R, lists,
This is an extremely helpful post, Gary, and I'm still in the process of
following up on it, but thought I'd better (rather than wait any longer)
mention some of the considerations it inspires with particular reference to
dicisigns.
First, your quote from CP 2.275-276 is originally from the "Speculative
Grammar" section of the Syllabus (EP2:272-3) immediately preceding Peirce's
introduction of the Dicisign as part of the "second trichotomy of
representamens" (EP2:275). Your next quote, CP 1.539, is from the Lowell
Lectures which the Syllabus was intended to accompany. But your third, CP
1.480 (about "genuine triads"), is from the "Logic of Mathematics" paper
c.1896. It occurs to me that Peirce's concept of a fact, or his usage of the
word, may have shifted somewhat during the intervening years.
In "Kaina Stoicheia" (1904?), Peirce wrote that "What we call a "fact" is
something having the structure of a proposition, but supposed to be an
element of the very universe itself." Earlier on, he wrote that
representation is necessarily triadic because "it involves a sign, or
representamen, of some kind, outward or inward, mediating between an object
and an interpreting thought. Now this is neither a matter of fact, since
thought is general, nor is it a matter of law, since thought is living" (CP
1.480, emphasis altered). This seems to imply that a "matter of fact" lacks
the generality of "thought", as if the universe of which it is "supposed to
be an element" is only the universe of existence, i.e. of Secondness. By
shifting the emphasis (in his definition of "fact") from that Secondness to
its structure - which is that of a proposition or dicisign, and therefore
partakes of Thirdness - I think Peirce was adding another dimension to the
mode of being of "fact".
But I'm not sure how much sense this makes, yet . I think it's related to a
some other pieces of the puzzle of the "genuine" which turn up in this
neighborhood. One is that although in KS the index is a degnerate sign,
relative to the symbol, it also seems to be true that the linguistic symbol
at least, if related to its object mainly by reference, involves a
degenerate index: the Index is a "Representamen whose Representative
character consists in its being an individual second. If the Secondness is
an existential relation, the Index is genuine. If the Secondness is a
reference, the Index is degenerate" (EP2:274). This shows at least that
genuineness and degeneracy are not absolute qualities but always relative to
a function. So even though Peirce gave the icon and index the "disparaging
name" of "degenerate" in KS, he also pointed out that they (especially when
combined!) can carry out semiotic functions that the symbol is incapable of
except by involving them.
The more we take the concept of "degeneracy" back to its purely mathematical
roots, the less disparaging it appears. For instance, we could describe a
circle as a degenerate ellipse, which only means that it is simpler than an
ellipse. I wonder, too, if the dicisign and the proposition itself can be
described as "degenerate" relative to the argument, which is the most
complete and complex of all sign-types because it separately indicates its
interpretant - and which, for that very reason, can only be a symbol. Is
that the main reason why the symbol is the most genuine member of the first
(icon/index/symbol) trichotomy of signs?
It's difficult to hold all these pieces of the puzzle in mind long enough to
see how it all fits together, and there's much in the latter part of your
post that I haven't dealt with here. But I think the joint effort should be
helpful toward a deeper and more exact understanding of Peirce's doctrine of
the Dicisign.
gary f.
From: Gary Richmond [mailto:***@gmail.com]
Sent: 26-Sep-14 3:51 PM
To: ***@lists.ut.ee
Cc: Peirce List
Subject: Re: [biosemiotics:7008] RE: [PEIRCE-L] Natural Propositions,
Chapter 3.3
Gary F., lists,
This is a very helpful outline of this section, Gary, which, along with the
next, 3.4, seems to me to be at the heart of this chapter, perhaps even at
the heart of NP itself. I've nothing to add or emend to what you've written,
and so I'll move immediately to your now twice asked and doubly vexing
question:
GF: "if a genuine dicisign or "indexical proposition" does not have to be
symbolic in order to fulfill its function of conveying information, why does
Peirce identify the symbol with the genuine sign?"
You conclude the substantive part of your post by giving Peirce's late
definition of a symbol as "a sign which is fit to serve as such simply
because it will be so interpreted" (EP2:307) then commenting:
GF: "Now, the icon/index/symbol trichotomy is supposed to be the list of
possible relations between sign (representamen) and object. Yet this
definition of symbol, on the face of it, seems to be more about the sign's
relation with its interpretant than with its object. No wonder the relation
between dicisign and symbol seems so complex.
Now as to the symbol seeming "to be more about the sign's relations with its
interpretant than with its object," I find the following quotation
suggestive (and, in consideration of the representamen, increasingly so as I
proceed down the ensuing group of quotes):
. . . . The most fundamental [division of signs] is into Icons, Indices, and
Symbols. Namely, while no Representamen actually functions as such until it
actually determines an Interpretant, yet it becomes a Representamen as soon
as it is fully capable of doing this; and its Representative Quality is not
necessarily dependent upon its ever actually determining an Interpretant,
nor even upon its actually having an Object (emphasis added).
An Icon is a Representamen whose Representative Quality is a Firstness
of it as a First. That is, a quality that it has qua thing renders it fit to
be a representamen. Thus, anything is fit to be a Substitute for anything
that it is like. (The conception of "substitute" involves that of a purpose,
and thus of genuine thirdness.) [emphasis added CP 2.275-276]
So the first hint here is that a representamen, while not actually
functioning as such, is indeed one "as soon as it is fully capable of
[determining an interpretant]. So, an icon is serving as a representamen
when it merely may substitute for something which it's like, AND the idea of
substitution involves that of purpose, "and thus of genuine thirdness."
But stepping back a bit from signs to categorial thirdness itself, Peirce
writes something telling here in suggesting that logic perhaps "ought to be
the science of Thridness in general":
Now it may be that logic ought to be the science of Thirdness in
general. But as I have studied it, it is simply the science of what must be
and ought to be true representation, so far as representation can be known
without any gathering of special facts beyond our ordinary daily life. It
is, in short, the philosophy of representation (CP 1.539).
But philosophy is the work of human minds. Yet, since thirdness involves
secondness and firstness, and since anything which involves the idea of
"purpose" (even the icon as the likeness of something) expresses "genuine
thirdness" (CP2.276), it would seem that to the extent that the dicisign
expresses purpose (which I think it clearly does) it expresses thirdness
even when it is not the symbolic variety of that sign.
Peirce also comments on "genuine triads" in a way which might be pertinent
to this inquiry. He begins the next passage with language seemingly
contradicting that which he used directly above--but note the conclusion of
the passage).
Genuine triads are of three kinds. For while a triad if genuine cannot
be in the world of quality nor in that of fact, yet it may be a mere law, or
regularity, of quality or of fact. But a thoroughly genuine triad is
separated entirely from those worlds and exists in the universe of
representations. Indeed, representation necessarily involves a genuine
triad. For it involves a sign, or representamen, of some kind, outward or
inward, mediating between an object and an interpreting thought. Now this is
neither a matter of fact, since thought is general, nor is it a matter of
law, since thought is living (CP 1.480, emphasis added).
So, every genuine triad "[involving] a sign, or representamen, o
f
some kind, outward or inward" (even the now near proverbial "sunflower")
has the potential to become a living thought (see CP 2.276 above). So the
idea of genuine thirdness, the genuine triad, may trump , in certain cases,
the idea of the genuine sign, which is to say the sign completed in its
being interpreted, that is, the symbol.
So, as the following quote concludes, "take away the psychological or
accidental human element, and in this genuine Thirdness we see the operation
of a sign," and 'philosophy' as such has nothing to do with it.
Now in genuine Thirdness, the first, the second, and the third are all
three of the nature of thirds, or thought, while in respect to one another
they are first, second, and third. The first is thought in its capacity as
mere possibility; that is, mere mind capable of thinking, or a mere vague
idea. The second is thought playing the role of a Secondness, or event. That
is, it is of the general nature of experience or information. The third is
thought in its role as governing Secondness. It brings the information into
the mind, or determines the idea and gives it body. It is informing thought,
or cognition. But take away the psychological or accidental human element,
and in this genuine Thirdness we see the operation of a sign (CP1.537).
So, whether or not it is possible that "logic ought to be the science of
Thirdness in general," for me the dicisign concept suggests that this idea
might have some resonance in biosemiotics, or perhaps that semiotics
generally ought be tempered by this idea (or something like it).
Finally, Peirce makes a distinction which may make a difference in this
direction of analysis by defining a sign as "anything which conveys any
definite notion of any object in any way":
. . . I use these two words, sign and representamen, differently. By a sign
I mean anything which conveys any definite notion of an object in any way,
as such conveyers of thought are familiarly known to us. Now I start with
this familiar idea and make the best analysis I can of what is essential to
a sign, and I define a representamen as being whatever that analysis applies
to. [. . . ] All signs convey notions to human minds; but I know no reason
why every representamen should do so (CP1.540, emphasis added).
And this is immediately followed by the following famous definition (which,
note in the context of what I just quoted, is a definition of a
representamen and not of a sign):
My definition of a representamen is as follows:
A REPRESENTAMEN is a subject of a triadic relation TO a second, called its
OBJECT, FOR a third, called its INTERPRETANT, this triadic relation being
such that the REPRESENTAMEN determines its interpretant to stand in the same
triadic relation to the same object for some interpretant (CP1.541).
I am not prepared to draw any definitive conclusions from the above which
are just some preliminary thoughts I had today. In short, I offer these
quotes and comments as suggestions towards a possible answer to the
intriguing question you asked, Gary. For all I know I may be heading in the
wrong direction.
Best,
Gary